Mostrar mensagens com a etiqueta Século XVIII. Mostrar todas as mensagens
Mostrar mensagens com a etiqueta Século XVIII. Mostrar todas as mensagens

quarta-feira, janeiro 23, 2008

Ver através / Visões mediadas

"Espelho Negro" ou "de Claude", portátil, gravura reproduzida em Arnaud Maillet, Le Miroir Noir. Enquête Sur le Côté Obscur du Reflet, Paris, Kargo & l'Éclat, 2005, pág. 19

Thomas Gainsborough (1727-1788), "Homem segurando um espelho", British Museum, Londres, reproduzido em Le Miroir Noir. Enquête Sur le Côté Obscur du Reflet, Paris, Kargo & l'Éclat, 2005, pág. 21

"Camera Obscura" portátil, proposta por Johannes Kepler (1571 - 1630) na década de 1620, reproduzida em H. Gernsheim, The Origins of Photography, Oxford, The Oxford University Press, 1955

"Camera Obscura" portátil de utilização militar, fotografia anotada "Hamilton Field, California" e datada "9/16/35"

Mais informação, "online", em Arnaud Maillet, Le Miroir Noir (2005), Sylvain Jouty, "Naissance de l'Altitude" (1999) e Jonathan Crary, Techniques of the Observer (1990).

segunda-feira, janeiro 21, 2008

O império da visão

Claude Nicolas Ledoux (1736-1806)), Teatro de Besançon, 1775-1784


According to Michel Foucault, the great project of this thought is an exhaustive ordering of the world characterized by "discovery of simple elements and their progressive combination; and at their center they form a table on which knowledge is displayed contemporary with itself. The center of knowledge in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries is the table. ''(68). Ernst Cassirer's reading of the Enlightenment, though unfashionable now, more than echoes certain parts of Foucault's construction of "classical thought." While much Anglo-American intellectual history tends to pose an atomization of cognition in this period, Cassirer sees a Leibnizian underpinning to eighteenth-century thought:

With the advent of the eigbteenth-century the absolutism of the unity principle seems to lose its grip and to accept some limitations or concessions. But these modifications do not touch the core of the thought itself. For the function of unification continues to be recognized as the basic role of reason. Rational order and control of the data of experience are not possible without strict unification. To "know" a manifold of experience is to place its component parts in such a relationship to one another that, starting from a given point, we can run through them according to a constant and general rule… the unknown and the known participate in a "common nature."(69)


Cassirer might well have agreed with Foucault that observation in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries is "a perceptible knowledge." 70) But it is hardly a knowledge that is organized exclusively around visuality. Although the dominance of the camera obscura paradigm does in fact imply a privilege given to vision, it is a vision that is a prlori in the service of a nonsensory faculty of understanding that alone gives a true conception of the world. It would be completely misleading to pose the camera obscura as an early stage in an ongoing autonomization and specialization of vision that continues into the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Vision can be privileged at different his- torical moments in ways that simply are not continuous with one another. Sit- uating subjectivity within a monolithic Western tradition of scopic or specular power effaces and subsumes the singular and incommensurable procedures and regimes through which an observer has been constituted.(71) For example, Berkeley's theory of perception is based on the essential dissimilarity of the senses of vision and touch, but this insistence on the heterogeneity of the senses is remote from nineteenth-century notions of the autonomy of vision and the separation of the senses.(72) Berkeley is hardly alone in the eighteenth century in his concern with achieving a fundamental harmonization of the senses, in which a key model for visual perception is the sense of touch. The Molyneux problem, which so preoccupied the thought of the eighteenth century, poses the case of a perceiver who is ignorant of one of the languages of the senses, namely sight. The best known formulation of the problem is Locke's:

Suppose a man born blind, and now adult, and taught by his touch to distinguish between a cube and a sphere of the same metal, and nighly of the same bigness, so as to tell, when he felt one and the other, which is the cube, which the sphere. Suppose then the cube and sphere placed on a table, and the blind man be made to see: quaere, whether by his sight before he touched them, he could now distinguish and tell which is the globe, which the cube?(73)


But regardless of how the problem was ultimately answered, whether the claim was nativist or empiricist, the testimony of the senses constituted for the eighteenth century a common surface of order.(74) The problem quite simply was how the passage from one order of sense perception to another took place.(75) Or for Condillac, in his famed discussion of the senses coming to life one by one in his statue, the problem was how the senses could "reconvene," that is, come together in the perceiver.(76) But for those whose answers to Molyneux were, in one way or another, negative - a blind man suddenly restored with sight would not immediately recognize the objects before him - and these included Locke, Berkeley, Diderot, Condillac, and others, they share little with the physiologists and psychologists of the nineteenth century who were also, with greater scientific authority, to answer the question negatively. By insisting that knowledge, and specifically knowledge of space and depth, is built up out of an orderly accumulation and cross-referencing of perceptions on a plane independent of the viewer, eighteenth-century thought could know nothing of the ideas of pure visibility to arise in the nineteenth century. Nothing could be more removed from Berkeley's theory of how distance is perceived than the science of the stereoscope. This quintessentially nineteenth-century device, with which tangibility (or relief) is constructed solely through an organization of optical cues (and the amalgamation of the observer into a component of the apparatus), eradicates the very field on which eighteenth-century knowledge arranged itself.
From Descartes to Berkeley to Diderot, vision is conceived in terms of analogies to the senses of touch.(77) Diderot's work will be misunderstood if we do not see at the outset how deeply ambivalent he was toward vision, and how he resisted treating any phenomenon in terms of a single sense,.78) His Letters on the Blind (1749), in its account of Nicholas Saunderson, a blind mathematician, asserts the possibility of a tactile geometry, and that touch as well as sight carries with it the capacity for apprehending universally valid truths. The essay is not so much a depreciation of the sense of vision as it is a refutation of its exclusivity. Diderot details Saunderson's devices for calculation and demonstration, rectangular wooden boards with built-in grids marked out by raised pins. By connecting the pins with silk threads Saunderson's fingers could trace out and read an infinity of figures and their relations, all calculable by their location on the demarcated grid. Here the Cartesian table appears in another form, but its underlying status is the same. The certainty of knowledge did not depend solely on the eye but on a more general relation of a unified human sensorium to a delimited space of order on which positions could be known and compared. (79) In a sighted person the senses are dissimilar, but through what Diderot calls "reciprocal assistance" they provide knowledge about the world. Yet despite this discourse on the senses and sensation, we are still within the same epistemological field occupied by the camera obscura and its overriding of the immediate subjective evidence of the body. Even in Diderot, a so-called materialist, the senses are conceived more as adjuncts of a rational mind and less as physiological organs. Each sense operates according to an immutable semantic logic that transcends its mere physical mode of functioning. Thus the significance of the image discussed in Diderot's letters on the Blind: a blindfolded man in an outdoor space steps forward, tentatively olding a stick in each hand, extended to feel the objects and area before him. But paradoxically this is not an image of a man literally blind; rather it is an abstract diagram of a fully sighted observer, in which vision operates like the sense of touch, just as the eyes are not finally what see, however, so the carnal organs of touch are also disengaged from contact with an exterior world. Of this blind and prosthesis-equipped figure that illustrated Descartes's La dioptrique Diderot remarks, "Neither Descartes nor those who have followed him have been able to give a dearer conception of vision."(80) This anti-optical notion of sight pervaded the work of other thinkers during both the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries: for Berkeley there is no such thing as visual perception of depth, and Condillac's statue effectively masters space with the help of movement and touch. The notion of vision as touch is adequate to a field of knowledge whose contents are organized as stable positions within an extensive terrain. But in the nineteenth century such a notion became incompatible with a field organized around exchange and flux, in which a knowledge hound up in touch would have been irreconcilable with the centrality of mobile signs and commodities whose identity is exclusively optical. The stereoscope, as I will show, became a crucial indication of the remapping and subsumption of the tactile within the optical.

[Notas]
66. Martin Heidegger, "The Age of the World Picture," in The Question Concernlng Technology and Other Essays, trans. William Lovin (New York, 1977), pp. 115-54.
67. Descartes, "Rules for lhe Direction of the Mind," in Philosophical WrItings, pp. 19, 21
68. MichelI Foucault, The Order of Things (New York, 1970), pp. 74-75. On Leibniz and the table, see Gilles Deleuze, Le pli, p. 38.
69. Ernst Cassirer, The Phllosophy of the Enllghtenment, trans. Fritz Koehn and James P. Pettegrove (Princeton, 1951), p. 23. An alternative continental reading of this aspect of eighteenth-century thought is Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. John Cumming (New York, 1979). For them, the quantitative "unity" of Enlightenment thought was continuous with and a precondition for the technocratic domination of the twentieth century. "In advance, the Enlightenment recognized as being and occurrence only what can be apprehended in unity : its ideal is the system front which all and everything follows. Its rationalist and empiricist versions do not part company on that point. Even though the individual schools may interpret the axioms differently, the structure of scientific unity has always been the same… The multiplicity of forms is reduced to position and arrangement, history to fact, things to maner" (p. 7).7
70. Foucault, The Order of Things, p. 132. On the problem of perception in Condillac and Diderot, see Suzanne Gearhart, Open Boundary of Fiction and History: A Critical Approach to the French Enlightenment (Princeton, 1984), pp. 161-199.
71 See Martin Jay, "Scopic Regimes of Modernity," in Vision and Vlisuality, ed. Hal Foster (Seattle, 1988), pp. 3-27.
72 Anglo-American criticism often tends to posit a continuous development of eighteenth-century thought into nineteenth-century empiricism and associationism. A typical account is Maurice Mandelbaum, History. Man and Reason: A Study In Nineteenth Century Thought (Baltimore, 1971, especially pp. 147-162. After insisling on a continuity between the thought of Locke, Condillac, and Hartley and nineteenth-century associationism, Mandelhaum concedes, "Thus, in its origins, associationism was not what James Mill and Alex- ander Bain later sought to make of it, a full-blown psychological system, serving to classify and relale all aspects of mental life; it was, rather, a principle used to connect a general epislemological position with more specific issues of intellectual and practical concern. Among these issues, questions concerning the foundations of morality and the relations of morality to religion had an especially important place" (p. 156). However, what Mandelbaum terms "a general epislemological position" is preciselyt he relative unity of Enlightenment knowledge onto which he imposes the separations and categories of the thought of his own lime. Religion, morality and epislemology did not exist as discrete and separate domains.
73. John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanng, II, ix, 8.
74. For example, see Thomas Reid, Essays on the Powers of the Human Mind [178S] (Edinburgh, 1819), vol. 2, pp. 115-116: "If any thing more were necessary to be said on a point so evident, we might observe, that if the faculty of seeing were in the eye, that of hearing in the ear, and so of the other senses, the necessary consequence of this would be, that the thinking principle, which I call myself, is not one but many. But this is contrary to the irresistable conviction of every man. When I say, I see, I hear, I fed, I remember, this implies that it is one and the same self that performs all these operalions."
75. See Cassirer, The Phillosophy of the Enlightenment, p. 101. For recent discussions of the problem, see M. J. Morgan, Molyneux's Question: Vision, Touch and the Philosophy of Perception (Cambridge, 1977); and Francine Markovits, "Mérian, Diderot et l'aveugle," in J.-B. Mérian, Sur le problème de Molyneux (Paris, 1984), pp. 193-282.
76. Etienne de Condillac, ''Trailé des sensations" (1754), in Oeuvres philosophiques de Condillac, vol. I, ed Georges Le Roy (Paris, 1947-1951).
77. See Michel Serres, Hermès ou la communication (Paris, 1968), pp. 124-125; and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Primacy of Perception, ed. James M. Edie (Evanston, Ill., 1964), pp. 169-172.
78. On Dlderot's attitude toward the senses, see Ellsabeth de Fontenay, Diderot. Reason and Resonance, transl. Jeffrey Mehlman (New York, 1982), pp. 157-169.
79. On the persistence of Cartesianism in Enlightenment thought, see Aram Vartanian, Diderot and Descates: A Study of Scientific Naturalism In the Enlightenment (Princeton: 1953)
80. Diderot asserts that the person most capable of theorizing on vision and the senses would be "a philosopher who had profoundly meditated on the subject in the dark, or to adopt the language of the poets, one who had put out his eyes in order to be better acquainted with vision." Lettres sur les aveugles, in Oeuvres philosophiques, p. 87.
Jonathan Crary, Techniques of the Observer: On Vision and Modernity in the Nineteenth Century, Cambridge (Mass.)-London, MIT Press, 1990, pp. 57-62

A página Origins of Modern Visual Culture, de Jonathan Crary, no site da Columbia University, tem vários recursos interessantes, sendo, porém, raros os universalmente acessíveis (isto é, sem "password"). Language as Vision: The Ocularcentrism of Chomskyan Linguistics, de Chris Werry, centra a questão estudada por Crary no texto acima reproduzido no território da linguística. Poderá ser útil a consulta das notas de leitura da obra citada de Crary, por Ron Broglio e por Garnet Hertz.

Ilustração para La Dioptrique (1637), de René Descartes (1596-1650)

segunda-feira, janeiro 07, 2008

Barroco: arqueologias e circulações de um vocábulo

Bartholomeus van der Helst, "Retrato de Anna du Pire como Granida", 1660, óleo sobre tela, 70 x 58,5 cm, Národní galerie, Praga

"Si nos remontamos al primer diccionario de la lengua francesa en donde apareció el término por vez primera, en 1690 como es el de Furetière, barroco lo definía de esta manera: 'Es un término de joyería que se aplica a las perlas que no son perfectamente redondas'.

En portugués, barroco se emplea para designar la perla irregular, tal como lo dice García de Orta en los Coloquios dos Simples e drogas da Indias (10). 'Huns barrocos mal afeiçoados e ñao redondos, e com aguas mortas' coloquios fechados en 1563. Se trataba pues, de esas perlas barrocas que los portugueses cultivaban y exportaban desde Broakti o Baroquia de las Indias.

La palabra berrueco que equivale a barroco en castellano se usa también en el segundo tercio del siglo XVI, en el lenguaje de las joyerías. En el Tesoro de la lengua Castellana de Covarrubias (1611), barrueco designa a la perla irregular y berrueco denomina al peñón granítico, y de allí surge 'berrocal, tierra áspera, y llena de berruecos que son peñascales levantados en alto: y de allí entre las pérolas ay unas mal proporcionadas y por la similitud le llaman berruecos'.

Luego de estos nombres rocosos, nudosos, tumorales, quistosos y proliferantes, barroco pasó a ser una figura de silogismo. Tal vez Barroco proviene del nombre de un pintor alumno de los Carraci, Federico Barocci (1528-1612) discípulo quizás muy amanerado (Sarduy, 1972).

Ya para 1711 comienzan sus matices despreciativos, pues Saint-Simon lo utilizó en sus Mémoires con un sentido de extraño y chocante.

La misma definición que dio Furetière en su Dictionnaire Universel de 1690, fue recogida en el Dictionnaire de l´Académie Francaise en su primera edición de 1694: 'Barroco, adjetivo. Se dice solamente de las perlas que tienen una redondez bastante imperfecta. Un collar de perlas barrocas'. En la edición de 1740 introducía el sentido figurado: 'Barroco se dice también en lo figurado para lo irregular, bizarro, desigual. Un espíritu barroco, una expresión barroca'.

En la Encyclopédie, en su suplemento de 1776, firmado por Rousseau dice: 'Barroco, en música; una música barroca es aquella cuya armonía es confusa, cargada de modulaciones y disonancias, la entonación es difícil y el movimiento violento'.

Las adjetivaciones peyorativas con respecto al barroco continúan profiriéndose en 1788. Quatremère de Quince, escribe en la Encyclopédie Méthodique: 'Barroco, adjetivo. El barroco en arquitectura es matiz de bizarro y lo es en el refinamiento y en el abuso. Lo que la severidad es a la sabiduría del gusto, el barroco lo es a lo bizarro, es decir, es su superlativo. La idea de barroco entraña en sí la del ridículo llevado al exceso'.

En el siglo XVIII, Francesco Milizia privilegiando a las artes clásicas retoma las expresiones de Quatremère de Quincy para definir al barroco en su Dizionario delle belle arti del disegno publicado en 1797: 'Barocco é il superlativo del bizarro, l´ecceso del ridicolo'.

(10) Citado por Victor L. Tapié, Baroque et Classicisme, París: Le livre de Poche, Col. “Pluriel», s.f."
Alejandro García Malpica, "Teorías del Barroco", Mañongo , nº 23, Año XII, Vol. XII, Julio-Diciembre 2004

Acrescento, a propósito da citação de Orta, o "link" para uma bem equipada biblioteca de mineralogia: no "site" da Farlang - Gems & Diamond Foundation.

sexta-feira, fevereiro 10, 2006

O segundo capítulo da modernidade

O FIM DO "CICLO CLÁSSICO"
c. 1750 - c. 1850

A ARTE E A CIVILIZAÇÃO INDUSTRIAL


Joseph Wright of Derby, Experiência com um Pássaro, 1768, National Gallery, London

O século XVIII acabará por substituir um modelo artístico único (o "Antigo") por uma multiplicidade de modelos de origens diversas. Todos se distinguem do presente (a "Antiguidade" já não é uma ressuscitada "Bela Adormecida", a mesma que os "Bárbaros" tinham morto e enterrado). Cada pólo, "classicista" ou "romântico", se multiplica em variadas opções (neo-palladiano, grego, romano, egípcio / gótico, mourisco, românico, barroquizante): o modelo único não só ganhou companhia como se dividiu internamente, sobretudo a partir da distinção entre cultura romana e cultura grega. As várias opções podem associar-se num mesmo objecto (ecletismo) ou ser usadas em objectos diferentes (o mesmo arquitecto poderá usar o modelo romano para projectar um tribunal e um modelo medieval para projectar uma igreja).

A Ciência (racional, crítica, experimental, matematizada) perfila-se como o único modelo de conhecimento. A máquina irá redefinindo a organização do trabalho e do território e transformará a percepção do mundo. A Lei substitui o Rei. A cultura responderá aceitando ou rejeitando as transformações, profetizando o Progresso ou a Decadência.

Em 1712 Thomas Newcomen patenteia uma máquina a vapor, aperfeiçoada, em 1769, por James Watt. Em 1776 as colónias americanas do Reino Unido tornam-se estados republicanos independentes - e em 1789 a França (adoptando o branco, vermelho e azul da bandeira americana - que as herdara da bandeira britânica) torna-se republicana.

Este segundo capítulo da modernidade finaliza movimentos civilizacionais começados, alguns (como a indústria), no final da "Idade Média" e inicia a destruição da civilização humanista herdada do "Renascimento" - destruição de que a "pós-modernidade" representa a consciência.

A cultura artística oscilará entre, por vezes acumulando-os no mesmo objecto, o "Neo-Classicismo" e o "Romantismo", duas faces da mesma moeda. Clique na imagem para tornar legível o confronto esquemático dos dois pólos:



Novo "link" (em "Imprensa"): Nineteenth-Century Art Worldwide, um excelente periódico sobre a cultura visual oitocentista - vem muito a propósito o artigo dedicado ao pintor Jacques-Louis David (1748-1825).

sexta-feira, janeiro 27, 2006

Feliz Aniversário, Wolfgang!

Retrato da família Mozart por Johann Nepomuk della Croce, 1780

"'Não!' gritei. 'Então o Senhor não entende? (...) Eu não quero outra coisa senão expiar, expiar, expiar, enfiar a cabeça debaixo da guilhotina e deixar-me castigar e aniquilar!'
Mozart encarou-me com insuportável ironia.
'Isto é que você é patético, hã! Mas ainda há-de vir a aprender a galhofar, a ter humor. O humor é sempre humor e, se for preciso, há-de aprendê-lo mesmo no cadafalso'.
(...) Subitamente lampejou-me diante dos olhos uma inscrição:

Execução de Harry

e eu baixei a cabeça em sinal de assentimento. (...) O acusador descobriu-se e pigarreou, todos os outros senhores tossicaram também. Depois, pegando num pomposo documento que desdobrou diante dos olhos, passou a ler:
'(...) Pelo que foi dito, se condena Haller à pena de vida eterna e à suspensão por doze horas do direito de admissão no nosso teatro. O réu também não poderá ser dispensado da pena de motejo. Meus senhores, façam favor de me acompanhar: um - dois - três!'
E, aos três, todos os presentes, em irrepreensível entrada, largaram a rir, gargalhada uníssona, riso terrífico do além que um ser humano mal pode suportar.
(...)
Quando voltei a mim, Mozart continuava sentado ao meu lado (...). 'Tem de aprender a ouvir a maldita música radifónica da vida, tem de venerar o espírito subjacente a ela, de levar em zombaria a fantochada que ela tem (...)'.
Baixinho, semi-cerrando os dentes, perguntei: 'E se eu recusar? (...)'
'Nesse caso', respondeu Mozart amenamente, 'propunha-te que fumasses mais um dos meus agradáveis cigarros'" (Hermann Hesse, O Lobo das Estepes, Porto, Edições Afrontamento, 1982).

(Mozart-Archiv der Internationalen Stiftung Mozarteum)

"Milan, Feb. 10, 1770.

SPEAK of the wolf, and you see his ears! I am quite well, and
impatiently expecting an answer from you. I kiss mamma's hand,
and send you a little note and a little kiss; and remain, as
before, your----What? Your aforesaid merry-andrew brother,
Wolfgang in Germany, Amadeo in Italy.

DE MORZANTINI."
Wolfgang Amadeus Mozart, Carta de 10 de Fevereiro de 1770, no Gutenberg Project

Anotações para a Flauta Mágica (1791), no "Diário Musical" de Wolfgang (1784-91).

Mais de 24 horas de Mozart - Sexta e Sábado, 27 e 28, no canal Mezzo. Depois da TV Cabo nos ter literalmente roubado o canal Arte do serviço básico, as comemorações televisivas, sem antena de satélite e sem aceitar o jogo sujo da empresa da PT, têm aí o único bastião.